Monday, October 29, 2012

Book Review: David Hollenbach's "The Common Good and Christian Ethics"


The Common Good and an Uncommon Response

What’s at Stake?
            Is the common good a “dead issue” in the minds of most Americans today?  Has toleration pushed questions of morality and religion into the private and “non-public” realms of society? (see pgs. 24-25) Does pursing a united vision of the common good risk neglecting or even coercing the values of other religions or traditions?  In many ways, the answer is “yes” to these questions.  But David Hollenbach demonstrates in The Common Good and Christian Ethics that even with these challenges, all is not yet lost in regards to the common good.  Hollenbach has hope that a Christian approach of “dialogic universalism” can greatly contribute to a shared national and global vision of the common good.  And he has such hope because of his basic conviction in the interrelatedness of human beings to each other.  This communal emphasis on human nature provides a strong foundation on which to build a vision of the common good.  The paper will thus argue that Hollenbach’s basic conviction of human nature provides a robust and compelling way forward specifically in pressing urban and global issues of the common good.  Further, where Hollenbach’s application may require further detail or nuance, the paper will capitalize on Hollenbach’s own opening of the door to the resources of the Calvinist and Lutheran theological traditions to suggest that Christian disciples must play a decisive role in formulating and implementing a vision of the common good.

The Necessity of a Vision of the Common Good
            Hollenbach argues in chapter 2 that the problems of urbanism and globalism are too big for the Western dominant values of tolerance and non-judgmentalism.  While toleration has helped form a society committed to equality, it fuels a suspicion that pursuing a stronger notion of the common good will lead to oppression and violence (pg. 32).  While carefully recognizing the inherent dangers of the common good in terms of coercion, Hollenbach demonstrates that historical examples of such coercion need not negate the positive possibilities of the common good.  What’s more, a vision of the common good is necessary to take our nation and world beyond the stalemate of tolerance.  For example, while tolerance has done much to open avenues of healing and opportunity among some of the urban poor, it has also left too many political and economic structures in place that continue to exclude the urban poor from participating in the fullness of life.  In terms of race, Hollenbach points out that even after the great gains of tolerance and acceptance from the Civil Rights Movement, there is a paradox in America today: “it is the best of times for the black middle class but among the worst of times for the poor blacks in America’s central cities” (pg. 41).  Tolerance has removed many of the personal barriers of racism, but it has left intact – and perhaps even strengthened – mentalities and structures that keep the poor ever poor.  Tolerance can perpetuate injustice through beliefs like “we make our own fate.”  For when the urban poor face the dire obstacles of inferior education, jobs with wages that cannot meet living standards, and the related behaviors of despair like drug-use, “making your own fate” can simply be too difficult a task.  A vision of the common good, however, can be strong enough to break even the societal structures that keep all but a few from making their own way.
            We need a vision of the common good because our current national values system is not up to the task of solving the problems we face as a society.  Hollenbach’s proposal of the common good can be a successful alternative because it is foundationally based in a strong conviction of what it means to be human.  Hollenbach traces the long tradition of the common good back through Ignatius, Thomas Aquinas, Augustine, Cicero, and Aristotle.  In these thinkers, the common good is based on how humans are connected to each other to form a society.  In Cicero’s republic, for example, it is presupposed that “persons are envisioned as bound together by strong connections” (pg. 65).  Hollenbach provides a theological explanation of Cicero’s insight, and in so doing shows how the common good can be both a Christian and universal concept.  In fact, he argues in chapter 5 that the promotion of a strong understanding of the civic good and full commitment to Christian faith are “essentially related” (pg. 113).  Augustine, for example, makes this argument using the concept of differentiation in The City of God: the Christian community is separated from the public square “without being either isolated from or dominant over it” (pg. 121).  Augustine is not looking for the church to control polity but he is also not interested in the church withdrawing from society.  Instead, the church, by its nature, strongly supports the virtues and values that are required in a republic (pg. 122).  The common good of the commonweal can only be realized when the people are “bound together by a love whereby each citizen loves his neighbor as he loves himself, for love of neighbor is the active work in the moral domain that gives expression to love of God” (pg. 123).  But Augustine is careful to distinguish what can be accomplished for the common good on earth and what is the eschatological hope of the city of God.  Hollenbach explains that Augustine’s emphasis on the transcendence of God rightly desacralizes politics; “it distinguishes what can be achieved politically from what Christians ultimately place their hope in” (pg. 125).  Certainly such an understanding is necessary to protect against the religious coercion that is one of dangers of pursing a notion of the common good.
            There is more to the church, however, than loving God and neighbor.  Thomas Aquinas (and Jacques Maritain’s social-political development of Aquinas’s ideas) can provide helpful grounding for a Trinitarian understanding of human nature and community.  Maritain, for example, “concludes that the essential relationality of personhood has its supreme exemplification in the unity of the three persons of the divine Trinity.  He follows Aquinas in affirming that the divine persons are “subsistent relations” – persons whose very identity as persons is their relationship one with the other” (pg. 131).  Now we begin to see the possibilities of deep theological interaction with the notion of the nature of persons as it relates to the common good.  If a defining attribute of personhood is contained in being in relation to the other (as it is in the Trinity), then, the common good becomes not just an idealistic pursuit, but a necessity.  If the Trinity serves as analogia entis, then we can rightly couple this with the Great Commandment to love God and love others to pursue a vision of the common good.  Now, certainly theologians debate whether Aquinas provides the best understanding of the Trinity, but, however we nuance the Trinity, it seems to me that if we try to base our understanding of personhood on anything less than God’s image, our pursuit of the common good can do nothing but fall short.

Implications of Intellectual Solidarity
            Hollenbach rightly places a great emphasis on the Catholic tradition of the common good.  His insights into the reforms of Vatican II, in particular, I think are incredibly valuable contributions to real solutions to the urban and global problems we face.  The Catholic idea of “dialogic universalism” does much to affirm the unique contributions of Christianity while affirming the necessity of deep intellectual and cultural exchanges (pg. 152ff).  I want to affirm Hollenbach’s work and suggestions in this area.  But I also want to pry open the door a bit more in terms of Hollenbach’s passing suggestions that Protestantism has some key resources to contribute to the notion of the common good, especially in the Calvinistic and Lutheran traditions.  Hollenbach briefly mentions these two traditions (see pages 116 and 150), but does little to engage their ideas.  Rather than fault him for this oversight (you can’t do everything in a book, after all), I want to pick up on his methodology and offer a few suggestions for how evangelicals might look to their own Protestant tradition for resources to help shape the vision of the common good.  What Hollenbach does affirm are the ideas of “orders of creation” and “common grace” in Calvin and Luther (even though their followers, he says, “are less confident in our ability to discern [these structures in creation] without the aid of revelation than are Catholics”) (pg. 150).  But I would argue that an evangelical appropriation of the common good that has a strong commitment to revelation would be an asset.  The Dutch neo-Calvinist tradition of Abraham Kuyper and Herman Bavinck, for example, relies significantly on the notion of common grace to affirm the pluriform structure of society.  In that God has revealed himself as sovereign over all, his grace sustains creation and supports human flourishing.  The role of the church is to shine its light brightly and broadly in the world and for the world.  But the church need not coerce the world to be the church.  God’s sustaining grace also affirms its multiform existence.  The church witnesses, but it also contributes to the “intellectual solidarity” of the global conversation of the common good. 
We can also look to the Lutheran tradition for similar insights.  In Ethics, Dietrich Bonhoeffer appropriates the Lutheran concept of the orders of creation to propose the four divine mandates of church, state, marriage and family, and culture.  The four mandates are not an outgrowth of history, or an expression of human power, but express “the reality of God’s love for the world and for human beings that has been revealed in Jesus Christ” (Bonhoeffer, Ethics, pg. 391).  Bonhoeffer coins the term “Christonomy” to explain the implications of his understanding of the mandates.  Christonomy, at its base, is a way to overcome the conflicting pressures of autonomy and heteronomy.  An autonomous view of reality, as Kuyper would also have contended, finds its triumph as each individual acts on his or her own free will.  On the other hand, heteronomy understands that actions are based upon external forces and obligations, like a principled Christian ethic.  Neither of these worldviews was, for Bonhoeffer, an accurate interpretation of reality.  Rather, reality is in Jesus Christ, and so individuals and societies are finally liberated and free to be with-one-another, for-one-another, and over-against-one-another.  The divine mandates exist to manifest this reality of freedom.  And this reality of freedom is a key to the formation of an understanding of the common good.  For Bonhoeffer, there is freedom and liberation for the church when it exists with, for, and over-against the state.  Likewise, the state flourishes when it can support culture, be in culture, and yet receive and incorporate culture’s critique.  All four mandates – church, state, family, and culture – and thus the major structures of society, reach their full potential when they operate in the reality of Jesus Christ, who is with, for, and over-against the world.  There are vast implications here for Christian discipleship in and for the world.  And my last word for Hollenbach would be that perhaps a greater emphasis on just this kind of for-others discipleship is the catalyst needed to address the political, economic, and societal structures plighting the poor and marginalized in our cities and across the globe.  A uniting notion of the common good can give vision to what’s possible, but Christian disciples have a unique obligation to make something of that vision.

No comments:

Post a Comment